Errata: Billingsley, Theorem 31.4

Jun. 18, 2014

This post will make sense only if you are reading along with a copy of Billingsley’s Probability and Measure, 3rd edition. This is for my future self and my brothers and sisters in Billingsley who may arrive here via Google.

At the beginning of the proof of Theorem 31.4 Billingsley says

… let An=(AI)A_n = \cap (A \cap I), where the intersection extends over the intervals I=(u,v]I=(u,v] for which u,vE,0<λ(I)<n1u,v \in E, 0<\lambda(I)<n^{-1}, and

μ(I)<(α+ϵ)λ(I)\mu(I)<(\alpha+\epsilon)\lambda(I)

A little thought shows that this cannot possible work. Take F(x)=xF(x)=x, α=2\alpha=2, A=A = \mathbb{R} and E=E=\mathbb{Q}. Then the intersection defined in AnA_n will be empty for all nn since for any xx\in \mathbb{R} there is an arbitrarily small interval IxI_x with rational end-points such that xIxx \notin I_x.

I think that the proof can be fixed if we replace the definition of AnA_n by

… let An=(AIc)A_n = \cap (A \cap I^c), where the intersection extends over the intervals I=(u,v]I=(u,v] for which u,vE,0<λ(I)<n1u,v \in E, 0<\lambda(I)<n^{-1}, and

μ(I)(α+ϵ)λ(I)\mu(I)\ge(\alpha+\epsilon)\lambda(I)

with the understanding that if there is no II meeting these conditions then An=AA_n=A.

The rest of the proof of part (i) can continue as it is. Under our new definition AnA_n is still a Borel set and it is now actually the case that AnAA_n \uparrow A.

After equation (31.20) we can argue that if InkI_{nk} does meets AnA_n it cannot be one of those II over whose complements the intersection is taken in the definition of AnA_n. But since InkI_{nk} has end-points in EE and λ(Ink)<n1\lambda(I_{nk})<n^{-1} it must then necessarily be the case that

μ(I)<(α+ϵ)λ(I)\mu(I)<(\alpha+\epsilon)\lambda(I)

This is what we need for the next displayed equation in the book.

The proof of part (ii) can be modified similarly.